Sep 16, 2022
"Graham Harman’s Architecture and Objects could very well be a new philosophical blueprint for how to build our emerging twenty-first-century world. By reconsidering the relationship between humanity, reality, and the built environment, he shows us, like a UV light at a crime scene, ways of understanding architecture that we’d never even considered but that are now, all of a sudden, glowing with brilliant potential." —Mark Foster Gage, Yale University and principal of Mark Foster Gage Architects
Full details.
Object-oriented ontology has become increasingly popular among architectural theorists and practitioners in recent years. Architecture and Objects, the first book on architecture by the founder of object-oriented ontology (OOO), deepens the exchange between architecture and philosophy, providing a new roadmap to OOO’s influence on the language and practice of contemporary architecture and offering new conceptions of the relationship between form and function.
Graham Harman opens with a critique of Heidegger, Derrida, and Deleuze, the three philosophers whose ideas have left the deepest imprint on the field, highlighting the limits of their thinking for architecture. Instead, Harman contends, architecture can employ OOO to reconsider traditional notions of form and function that emphasize their relational characteristics—form with a building’s visual style, function with its stated purpose—and constrain architecture’s possibilities through literalism. Harman challenges these understandings by proposing de-relationalized versions of both (zero-form and zero-function) that together provide a convincing rejoinder to Immanuel Kant’s dismissal of architecture as “impure.”
Through critical engagement with the writings of Peter Eisenman and fresh assessments of buildings by Rem Koolhaas, Frank Gehry, and Zaha Hadid, Architecture and Objects forwards a bold vision of architecture. Overcoming the difficult task of “zeroing” function, Harman concludes, would place architecture at the forefront of a necessary revitalization of exhausted aesthetic paradigms.
About the author.
Graham Harman is distinguished professor of philosophy at the Southern California Institute of Architecture, Los Angeles, and author of many books, including Speculative Realism: An Introduction and Object-Oriented Ontology: A New Theory of Everything.
raham Harman’s willingness—indeed, his pleasure—to immerse himself in the complexities of architectural history, theory, practice, and criticism results in a book that not only subtly translates between architecture and philosophy but, more provocatively, argues for architecture’s centrality in rethinking Kantian aesthetic formalism and its legacy in formalist art, criticism, and aesthetics. He offers us a compelling account of architecture as a drama of rifts and splits in the ‘zeroing’ of form, function, and time, while further elucidating the crucial role of aesthetics as ‘first philosophy’ in object-oriented ontology.
Contents
Introduction
1. Architects and Their Philosophers
2. I Know Not What
3. Object-Orientation
4. The Aesthetic Centrality of Architecture
5. The Architectural Cell
Concluding Maxims
Notes
Bibliography
Index
https://www.upress.umn.edu/book-division/books/architecture-and-objects
August:
Welcome to Philosophy podcast, where we interview leading
philosophers about their recent work. Today we're talking about the
book Architecture and Objects: Art After Nature by Graham Harmon.
The description is "Object-oriented ontology has become
increasingly popular among architectural theorists and
practitioners in recent years. Architecture and Objects," this
book, "the first book on architecture by the founder of OOO,
Object-Oriented Ontology, deepens the exchange between architecture
and philosophy, providing a new roadmap to OOO's influence on the
language and practice of contemporary architecture, and offering
new conceptions of the relationship between form and function.
Engaging with Heidegger, Derrida, Deleuze, writings of Peter
Eisenman, and buildings by Rem Koolhaas, Frank Gehry, and Zaha
Hadid, Graham Harmon forwards a bold vision of architecture, one
that places architecture at the forefront of a necessary
revitalization of exhausted aesthetic paradigms."
August:
A couple of the recommendations.
August:
Mark Foster Gage, Yale University. "Graham Harmon's Architecture
and Objects could very well be a new philosophical blueprint for
how to build our emerging 21st-century world. By reconsidering the
relationship between humanity, reality, and built environment, he
shows us, like a UV light at a crime scene, ways of understanding
architecture that we'd never even considered, but that are now all
of a sudden glowing with brilliant potential."
August:
Aron Vinegar of the University of Oslo. "Graham Harmon's
willingness, indeed his pleasure, to immerse himself in the
complexity of architectural history, theory, practice, and
criticism, results in a book that not only subtly translates
between architecture and philosophy, but more provocatively argues
for architecture's centrality in rethinking Kantian aesthetic
formalism. He offers us a compelling account of architecture as a
drama of rifts and splits in the zeroing of form, function, and
time."
August:
Graham Harmon is a distinguished professor of philosophy at the
Southern California Institute of Architecture. His books include
Art and Objects, and Object-Oriented Ontology: A New Theory of
Everything. Welcome, Professor Harmon.
Graham Harmon:
Thank you very much, August. It's a pleasure to be here.
August:
You start off your book by saying "why a book on architecture,
other than that I have recently been appointed to a architecture
school." I think that's your opening joke. How do you answer
that?
Graham Harmon:
I answer that by saying that this book is a continuation of my book
Art and Objects from two years earlier, in which I was trying to
express support for what's called Kantian formalism in the arts.
The idea that an artwork is cut off from other things, and needs to
be interpreted in its own rights, not in terms of its conceptual
meaning, not in terms of its socio-historical surroundings, not in
terms of how it personally makes us feel. I want to basically
express support for that while also pointing to the limitations of
Kantian formalism, which I did in that book, by pointing out that
Kant and some of his modern heirs in art criticism such as Michael
Fried, someone I admire very much, are two quick to dissociate the
artwork from the human beholder. I argued in that book there's no
way to do that, because artwork has to be seen as a composite or
hybrid made of the physical work and the person who encounters
it.
Graham Harmon:
Now, in Architecture and Objects I wanted to take up the fact that
Kant is quite down on architecture, ranks it very low in the arts.
The reason being that it's useful. If an artwork is useful, that's
just as bad as an ethical act being useful. Because, of course, in
Kant's ethics, ethical acts have to be performed for their own sake
not because they lead to any good results, or lead to a better
reputation for the person for being ethical, or lead to the person
going to heaven instead of hell.
Graham Harmon:
All of those things ruin the purity of an ethical act for Kant, and
likewise, for an artwork to be useful ruins the purity of the
beauty. I realized that the conclusion I reached in Art and Objects
allows us to rethink Kant's idea of architecture. Namely, since the
entanglement of the human and the artwork is no longer a problem in
my interpretation of visual art, that means that architecture is no
longer suspect. Because that entanglement already occurs at the
level of visual art, let alone at the level of architecture. It was
a chance to rethink architecture in a post-Kantian way that
nonetheless respects what Kant was seeing.
August:
Okay. I guess you clearly haven't gone through the other fields
that have both art and practical application, fashion design to
interior design to just being a hairdresser. I understand you make
an argument about the difference between architecture and art, and
you talk about the centrality of architecture. But it'll be another
project to think about how those other fields might rank.
Graham Harmon:
Yes. I mean, I could write a book about anything if I put myself to
it. Architecture just seemed more pressing both because Kant has
bad things to say about it, and also because I am working in
architecture school. I've been pressuring myself to learn a lot
about architecture over the past 10 years, but especially the last
7 that I've been teaching at an architecture school.
August:
I see. One of your statements in the book is that when an architect
makes a building, it's a tacit statement about the nature of
reality, and that provides a overlap with philosophy. That's not
clear to me why that would be true. Why, when an architect is
building a building, it is a statement or it is an attempt to
capture a deeper reality.
Graham Harmon:
My friend and colleague David Rue, I was undergraduate with him and
now on his colleague at SCI-Arc, made a very interesting statement
about 10 years ago in one of his articles, where he said that
architecture gives us our first sense of reality. It's quite rare
that any human is in the middle of raw nature. Even if you're in a
national park, you're in an organized space, at least the entrance
into the park has been arranged by civil engineers and landscape
designers. All the moreso if you're in a city, you're in a town.
Right now you're in a house, I'm in an apartment building. We are
not in direct confrontation with nature. We are inhabiting a
human-designed medium. Just as many animals primarily inhabit media
that they create themselves, whether it's beehives or beaver
dams.
Graham Harmon:
What this means is that our sense of reality is actually decided by
the architect. The architect can decide whether we're in a soothing
space or an ominous space, can decide whether we are in a space
that allows in lots of sunlight or not much sunlight. In more
recent architecture, the architecture can decide that the world is
basically homogeneous and smooth and curves gently from one thing
and another, or that there are abrupt cutoff points and different
fashions have held sway at different times.
Graham Harmon:
This is the sense in which architecture makes a tacit statement
about the nature of reality. On this basis, architects have picked
up different philosophers at different times, especially in the
last 60 years, to help guide their thinking. That itself is
controversial in the architectural world now. There are some
architects who think there's been too much philosophy and they want
to get back to disciplinary craft.
Graham Harmon:
In my book, I make the case that, look, architecture is already
involving all kinds of other disciplines. Why should you simply
decide to exclude philosophy? Architects are some of the most
omnivorous intellects I've encountered. They have to know about
everything. They have to learn about whatever it is that their
project is dedicated to. We'll always be a natural dialogue partner
for architects.
August:
I would assume there's a lot of variety across architects, so that
some architects would look for inspiration in philosophy and others
wouldn't. They might find it somewhere else, or they're feel the
muse is speaking through them. Is that true? A wide variety?
Graham Harmon:
Yes it is, and if you just look at recent architects, Peter
Eisenman is as much a theorist as he is an architect. He drew first
on Noam Chomsky, later on Derrida, later on Deleuze. He's picked up
all kinds of things that are interesting to him he writes
theoretical texts that I find interesting as a philosopher. I've
debated with some of them in my book. Then you've got Zaha Hadid,
the late lamented Zaha Hadid, who unfortunately died six years ago,
too young, who was one of the preeminent architects of recent
decades, but doesn't show much evidence of having been interested
in theory on the philosophy [inaudible 00:09:35]. And yet, she fits
very well within the Deleuzian current of architecture, even if I
don't know how much Deleuze she read, if any. But the kind of
design she does as a natural partner for Deleuze's philosophy. She
was called the Queen of the Curve. Everything is continuous. They
are very beautiful forms that she creates. They are also a
statement about the nature of reality, even if she wouldn't have
framed them that way.
August:
One of your concerns is clearly to, it seems that people have
started using your theory, or the theory that's associated with
you. Do you call it OOO?
Graham Harmon:
I pronounce it Triple O usually, but-
August:
Triple O? Okay. People have started to use that. You've seen it
being referred to in texts about architecture or in discussions. It
seems that one of your points was, "Okay, how do you do this in a
way that is not too superficial, not too literal?"
Graham Harmon:
I think literalism is itself a philosophical problem. One of the
themes of my book. Literalism you can define is the idea that a
thing is nothing more than all of the qualities that it possesses.
Philosophically, I guess the godfather of this idea is David Hume,
who says "there are no objects, there are just bundles of
qualities." There's not really any such thing as an apple. There's
just red, round, juicy, hard, cold, sweet. All of these things go
together so frequently that we form the habit of thinking of them
as one thing we call it an apple. But apple itself is really
nothing more for Hume and his followers than all of those things
put together. Whereas phenomenology in the 20th century, with
Husserl and beyond, Merleau-Ponty and others, says the opposite.
That an object is always more than its qualities, because it vary,
see different qualities of the thing at different times. Yet you
never stop thinking of it as one and the same thing.
Graham Harmon:
So, the path to literalism, first of all, is seeing that the object
is something distinct from its qualities, can change qualities and
still be the same thing. It can be split from its qualities and
still be the same thing. What interests me about aesthetics, which
is usually considered a minor side annex to philosophy. While the
big shots do metaphysics and epistemology and political theory.
Aesthetics, for me, is not just about art that cultured humans find
enjoyable. It's about a split between the object and its qualities.
Which I think is the fundamental philosophical problem, because you
can never pin down a thing in terms of definite qualities.
Aesthetics helps remind us of this. Aesthetic language play a much
larger role in Triple O than they do for other philosophies.
Because I don't think literalism works. I don't think you can get
the literal truth about the cosmos. Philosophy is not a
knowledge.
Graham Harmon:
I think even science, in a sense, is not a knowledge. Science is,
in large part, a knowledge. But we find in moments of what Kuhn
called paradigm shifts, science comes into crisis, that we're not
really sure anymore what the fundamental nature of reality is. Not
just Kuhn. I would make the same statement about Popper and
falsification, that science is, in many ways, a negative procedure
rather than a positive one. Knowledge, in a way, is what deep
thought opposes. Knowledge is a pragmatically useful thing. I
wouldn't want to live in the world without knowledge. We rely on
medical knowledge, we rely on engineering knowledge and so forth.
But the frontiers of thought are always somewhere other than
knowledge. They're at the place where we don't know something
yet.
August:
I think one of the things you're doing is saying, "Let's not
downplay something like metaphor." It's very insightful, actually.
I don't know. You talk about non-rationalism. I think of it as a
romantic current. Do you think of it that way?
Graham Harmon:
It could be. One difference from romanticism, which I admire a lot
about romanticism, is this notion of the sublime, and Triple O's
opposition to the sublime. Kant defines the sublime. He's talking
about things like standing and looking out at the stormy sea, or
looking up at the sky at night, maybe looking at these new photos
from the James Webb Space Telescope, that, I agree, with those
profound emotions unlocked by those moments. But Kant defines the
sublime as the absolutely large or the absolutely powerful. I'm
questioning the absolute part of it. Another Triple O theorist,
Timothy Morton, wrote on his book Hyperobjects, that in a way,
infinity is easily masterable. When you think about infinity, you
think, "Wow, I can think the infinite." You feel proud of yourself.
But Tim Morton says, "Try counting up to a hundred thousand."
That's a finite number, but in some ways that's a more realistic
threat than, say, infinity.
Graham Harmon:
And he primarily applied this to climate change, that it's somehow
less threatening to say infinity than to say that the half-life of
this material is 70,000 years or something. Because nobody in
70,000 years who's left, if anyone is left, I'm not going to have
any meaningful connection with any of those people. It will be a
totally different world. That's an idea I drew from Morton, to
critique the sublime, that things can seem infinite, but they're
actually all infinite in different ways and in different amounts.
That would be the difference from romanticism, the idea that each,
also the fact that in some ways romanticism fetishizes nature.
Triple O does not want to do [inaudible 00:15:04]. For Triple O,
technological objects are just as interesting as pine forests.
That's another departure from romanticism.
August:
I understand. That's a good point. I notice you go through the book
and you talk about how architects have used other philosophers and
it's Heidegger, Derrida, DeLeuze. It strikes the reader that these
are so-called continental philosophers. Even when you describe how
architects might want to look at/to philosophers for maybe a new
way of seeing things, that seems like more of a role for a
continental philosopher, to inspire provoke, rather than the, as I
understand the more analytic, let's be very clear and careful just
inscribing things, not trying to provoke or astonish. Would you
agree with that?
Graham Harmon:
I would, and this doesn't reflect even a value judgment on my part.
It's just the description of what architects are doing. Architects
are not really reading analytic philosophers. I'm not even sure
what analytic philosopher they might read to inspire new
architecture. Obviously Wittgenstein is of interest to everybody on
some level, and was also a fine architect himself. I had the chance
to tour his-
August:
I didn't know that.
Graham Harmon:
... house behind in Vienna. Which it's not generally accessible to
the public. It's the Bulgarian cultural attache's office or
something now in Vienna. But we had an architectural contact who
enabled us to make a tour of that house. I was with an architect
friend who said he thinks AR V Stein could have been one of the
great architects [inaudible 00:16:42] decided to be. It's a
remarkable piece of work. You'd think that Wittgenstein might
appear more in architectural discourse, but that hasn't really
happened the way it has in the visual arts with people like
Kossoth, who was very influenced by Wittgenstein. Stanley Cavel is
another person who writes well on the creation and has obviously
had some influence on arts and our criticism through his friend,
Michael fried. But I don't hear, Cavel mentioned by architects. I
hear the big continental names. Heidegger, [inaudible 00:17:10]
Deleuze, to a lesser extent Latour, Peter Sloterdijk has some
growing interest, though he hasn't really spawned a school yet.
Graham Harmon:
We could ask why that is. I think part of this analytic philosophy
made a decision early on. It is what it is. It made a decision to
constitute itself as a science. It emulates specialized scientific
disciplines. They take pride in this, in having very precise
terminology, in referring mostly to recent work by other analytic
philosophers, in dominating the departments of philosophy in the
Anglo-American world. At least the prestigious ones. If you want to
do continental philosophy like me, you end up going to small
Catholic universities or maybe a few state schools such as Penn
State or Memphis, Stony Brook, that do that kind of thing. But it's
largely a Catholic-
August:
Interesting.
Graham Harmon:
Because continental philosophy fits well, I think, with the
Catholic church's admirable support of the history of philosophy.
Even though most of the graduate students at these places are not
themselves Catholics. The Catholic universities support this very
nicely.
Graham Harmon:
The problem that analytic philosophy has created for itself,
there's two sides to every coin, is that it's not as accessible to
the general public. Indeed, I think it takes pride in that, that we
are a scientific discourse and just like the average person can't
read quantum theory articles in a journal, the average person
shouldn't expect to read analytic philosophy journals with
ease.
Graham Harmon:
All right, but there's a sense in which philosophy also needs to be
readable by the average intelligent person. This is something
continental philosophy, in principle, does better. In practice, a
lot of the professors in continental philosophy become just as
narrow in their writing, and also tend to be more
commentary-oriented sometimes. Rather than putting forth theories
of their own, they tend to comment on Heidegger or Kant [inaudible
00:18:55] their own theories. But people like Zizek are always
going to be more easily readable and perhaps more interesting for
the general public than, say, Timothy Williamson at Oxford, who's
one of the leading philosophers at Oxford, analytic philosophers,
or David Lewis. The deceased David Lewis, one of their great
meta-physicians. These are always going to be hard for the average
person to read. I think that's the issue with architecture.
August:
Some would say, well, I guess there's the famous Nusbaum article on
Butler where she says that some in the continental tradition
cultivate a mystique around being obscure. Do you see any merit in
that also? In some of the writing is very obscure.
Graham Harmon:
Sometimes. For example, I'm not an admirer of Derrida's style at
all. I find it to be a headache to read Derrida most of the time.
He gets into a groove once in a while, where he is got 8 or 10
pages that get right to the point. But that's usually preceded and
followed by lots of dancing that I find tedious. Judith Butler is
an interesting case. I just have to say this in defense of Butler.
I don't like how she writes. She writes very technically. She's not
as accessible as she could be. I think no spam made some fair
points about that in her article. Then I had the chance to meet
Judith Butler. She came over to Cairo, Egypt, as a guest speaker at
the university when I was there. She's really disarming. Because,
first of all, she's incredibly intelligent. There are certain
people you're just in their presence and you have the sense
immediately, "This is a very smart person."
Graham Harmon:
Second, she's an incredible listener. She looks you right in the
eye and listens to everything you say. It's unnerving in a way.
[inaudible 00:20:41] Judith Butler's listening to every word I say.
It's rare to meet people like that. I didn't get the sense she's
someone who cherishes obscurity as a person. Also, in the talk she
gave, which was simply on Palestinian-Israeli politics, she was
very clear. She didn't try to dither. She told us exactly what she
thought should be done, to this audience. Obviously pro-Palestinian
audience primarily in Egypt. I'm not sure why she chooses to write
that way. I don't like the excuses that are sometimes made for
that. They'll sometimes say, "Well, nobody complains that quantum
theory is hard to understand." The difference there, Michelle
Serres pointed this out, that in science, technical language is a
shortcut. It's a way of saying more using fewer words. Whereas
sometimes in the humanities, it's a way of saying less using more
words. I think Serres is right about that. This is why I think it's
very important to write clearly.
Graham Harmon:
I think one of the things about my generation in continental
philosophy is if you look at someone like Meillassoux, he's very
clear, very easy to read. I've talked to him about this. He said
that that was his explicit goal. He didn't like the way Derridans
wrote, he didn't like the way phenomenologists wrote even, and
simply wanted to be as clear as possible. I think all of us in
speculative realism made an effort to write clearly, to a greater
or lesser extent I think this was an excess of the, let's say,
post-structuralist generation of continental philosophy.
August:
We imitate our teachers, so something like a style can perpetuate
like that.
Graham Harmon:
Yes.
August:
Let's talk about Triple O. All right. This was the first time I saw
it. I actually just found your name by looking up leaving
philosophers.
Graham Harmon:
All right.
August:
Yeah. Object-Oriented Ontology. I think if someone asked me to
explain my understanding of it, in my words, I would say the idea
is basically we want to go against what you hear. Currently. You
hear this a lot in psychoanalysis, for example, about there is no
such thing as a person. There's just a bunch of connections with
other people. It's relationships come before the person, and
there's a big problem with thinking about a person as a unit that
goes through time. Triple O wants to talk about objects. That's the
first word. It wants to have a very broad view of objects.
August:
I think it's very much in the line of Socrates in the sense of
saying there's a lot that we don't know. It's also in line with
Kant saying there is this noumena behind reality that we can't
really access. I think it addresses the traditional problem in
philosophy, which is this idea that there's what we interact with,
then there's what things really are. That all our interactions are
mediated. Then there's this question about what is real, what is
underlying and real? It seems to me that Triple O addresses that.
Then I would say, addresses that basic question, but it doesn't
say, "Let's have a divide between consciousness and world, or mind
and world." It says, essentially, as I understand it, "we're going
to talk about objects, but we're not really going to put a subject
in the center. We're going to make the subject another object.
We're going to recognize an underlying or a deeper level, which is
real and a higher level, which we'll call sensual, which includes
much more than just sense perception."
August:
Then I think the other thing that it does is it says we're also
going to put some structure on this real realm. Which is to say
that there are, in this real realm, both objects and qualities.
That would be my take after reading this book, but feel free to
tell me I got it totally wrong.
Graham Harmon:
You got it totally right.
August:
Okay. Great.
Graham Harmon:
Nice summary. Very nice summary. Yes. You made a couple of
important points there that I need to respond to. First of all,
yes, we shouldn't reduce the thing either downward to its pieces or
upward to its effects that's a common ... First of all, let me say
that's what knowledge is. There are really only two kinds of
knowledge that humans can have. If I ask you what something is, you
can either tell me what it's made of or tell me what it does. There
are subcategories of each of these. You can tell me the history of
a thing, you can tell me its physical composition. These are all
ways of telling me what it's made of.
Graham Harmon:
Or you can tell me what it does. You can say that oxygen allows
living creatures to breathe, it causes fire to combust, things like
this. And all forms of knowledge involve explaining a thing in
terms of something else. That's fine. We need knowledge to survive
as a species.
Graham Harmon:
But knowledge does not exhaust human cognition. There is also a
human cognition that does a kind of mute justice, or tries to do a
kind of mute justice to things that goes beyond that. It's commonly
known, accepted by any philosophers if not all, that a thing is an
emergent thing beyond its components. Water is made of hydrogen and
oxygen, and it's great that we've known that since Lavoisier'
chemistry in the late 1700s. But obviously oxygen has properties
not found in either hydrogen or oxygen. It puts out fire, whereas
both hydrogen and oxygen combust fire, and so on. You need hydrogen
and oxygen to make fire, and you can even predict the properties of
water using quantum chemistry once you know what hydrogen and
oxygen are. But it's not a question of predictability. It's a
question of the thing, having an independent reality.
Graham Harmon:
The Los Angeles Dodgers baseball team is something over and above
each of the individual members, right? It has obviously not had the
same members for the whole 60 years. Players keep leaving, new
players come in, so the Dodgers are something over and above their
pieces. They're also something, I would say, under and beneath
their relations. Because new teams have been added to the league
since the Los Angeles Dodgers franchise relocated from Brooklyn to
Los Angele.s they have to play now the Colorado Rockies and the
Marlins who did not exist when the Dodgers first existed. The
Dodgers, they play in different stadiums than they used to. New
stadiums are being opened. So, the Dodgers, and obviously the
American society around the Dodgers and Los Angeles, these are all
changing. And yet the Dodgers, in some sense, remain the Dodgers.
You can't reduce them upward. Some kernel remains always there,
though never perfectly expressed in any given Dodgers game or any
given season.
Graham Harmon:
Those are what I call critiques of undermining and overmining. You
can undermine a thing by going downward, overmine it by going
upward, then those combine in what I call dual mining. Normal
scientific materialism, for example, is a dual mining gesture.
Because on the one hand, it says things are reducible to their
tiniest particles or the fields, whatever the smallest stuff is.
But then it also wants to say, "Yes, but this is all
mathematizable," which we can know. Therefore reducing it upward to
its knowledge. We're not taking account of any residue in the
things that's non-mathematizable, ever since Galileo and
Descartes.
Graham Harmon:
Object is something in between those two extremes, and you can't
know it by definition because any knowledge involves an undermining
or an overmining. So how do we get at it? Well, aesthetics is the
obvious answer, because when you're experiencing an artwork, you're
not telling the beholders what it's made of. I mean, you might as
some kind of dadaist gesture, but we're not primarily interested in
what an artwork is made of the way we are interested in what a rock
is made of in science. You're also not interested only in how this
artwork makes me feel, or how this artwork comments on contemporary
politics, because those things all change, and an artwork is
supposed to challenge me to perceive it differently. The better it
is, the more I'm going to have to go back to it and find things in
it that I didn't find first.
Graham Harmon:
An artwork's an obvious example, but then there's also philosophy,
which I think is closer to the arts than the sciences. Something
analytic philosophy would never like. Because philosophy is, of
course, philosophia. Possibly from Pythagoras onwards. Philosophia
means the love of wisdom, not wisdom. Philosophy is not a
knowledge. You get some analytic philosophers referring to what
they do as scientific philosophy or exact philosophy. I see those
as a contradiction in terms. That's like saying exact art, what
would exact art be? It misses the point.
Graham Harmon:
Socrates asks a lot about the definitions of things, but he never
gets any definitions. Every dialogue ends in further perplexity. He
always says, or at least a few times says, "The only thing I know
is I know nothing. I've never been anyone's teacher." So we
shouldn't see Socrates as a wise man or as a scientist. He's not.
He's a philosopher, and philosophy is something a little closer to
the arts than to science. I'll give one quote supporting this
that's often overlooked. Last great philosopher before the analytic
continental split was Franz Brentano, the teacher of Husserl. He
gave a very interesting lecture about philosophy in the 1890s in
Vienna. He made this point that's not been commented on often,
where he said, "In some senses, philosophy is like science. It
makes progress. Every generation should see things in philosophy
that the previous generation didn't. But in another sense, it's
like the fine arts. It has periods of ripeness and periods of
decline."
Graham Harmon:
You wouldn't necessarily say, even in analytic philosophy, that
analytic philosophy knows more in 2022 than it knew in the time of
Russell and Wittgenstein. In some sense, yes, because we have
critiques to Russell and Wittgenstein now. But in some sense, that
was a riper era. That was a more celebrated era of analytic
philosophy than 2022, I would say .just like you have in the arts.
2022 art is not necessarily better than high cubism, which was
considered a great period in modern art.
Graham Harmon:
Now, the question is how you reconcile those two. In many ways,
this was also the question that guided Thomas Kuhn in discussing
the history of science, the difference between normal science and
revolutionary science. What is the relation between those two?
Because normal science is cumulative. Then from time to time, it's
completely disrupted by paradigm shifts. This hasn't been applied
to philosophy enough, this idea that there are paradigm-shifting
periods in philosophy. German idealism remains one of the most
revered periods in the history of philosophy by scholars [inaudible
00:31:41] between Kant and Hegel that seems to embody philosophy to
an eminent degree. Lots of stuff was happening every year. That
isn't happening right now, as far as the public eye can see.
Right?
August:
Right.
Graham Harmon:
This seems like a fairly normal period in philosophy by
comparison.
August:
Well, take Socrates, Plato, Aristotle. There's three, they were
[inaudible 00:32:02] teachers.
Graham Harmon:
In Western philosophy this happens a lot. You also had Descartes,
Spinoza, Leibniz. In the UK you had Locke, Berkeley, Hume, and you
had Husserl, Heidegger, and-
August:
Brentano. Yeah. Okay.
Graham Harmon:
Yeah. I would add Brentano. I might add Scheler. You could
[inaudible 00:32:20] decrease the groups of. Oh, even in the
Medieval time you had Aquinas, Scotus, Occam. This seems to be a
common phenomenon in Western philosophy. I should say European
philosophy. If you go to Islamic philosophy, what jumps out at you
is that their lifetimes don't overlap. If you look at Al-Kindi,
Al-Farabi, Ibn Sina, Averroes, I don't think any of their lifetimes
overlap. There's small gaps between each of them.
August:
Interesting.
Graham Harmon:
I'm not sure what that means. I've been puzzling [inaudible
00:32:49] that for years, that they were spread out in time. I
think that gives a different topology to Islamic philosophy.
Whereas, yeah, in the European tradition, it's always bang, bang,
bang. Three or four people in a row. Often they knew each other
personally, at least some of them.
August:
And sometimes they were the student of the professor
Graham Harmon:
Quite often. That's right. Or at least met each other. Leibniz went
and met Spinoza for example.
August:
Brentano, Husserl, Heidegger, clearly.
Graham Harmon:
Exactly. Exactly. That's an interesting phenomenon. You see that in
the history of art as well, that the artists are grouped together
usually, in great periods, as though one unlocks the possibilities
of the next.
Graham Harmon:
Another interesting thing about those clusters, is that the first
person in the cluster always starts older, or almost always starts
older. It's as though it's harder for someone like Kant to dream up
the new principles of a new way of looking at philosophy. But then
once someone's put it out there, younger people can take it and
improve it or revolutionize it in some way. Hegel started much
younger than Kant. The Phenomenology of Spirit, he was in his, I
think, mid-thirties. [inaudible 00:34:00] wrote that. Whereas Kant
was in his late 50s, publishing the First Critique. Same with
Husserl and Heidegger.
August:
That's right. I imagine that, and you talk about this and I can
tell that you have gotten, this must be a common response to the
object-oriented ontology. It sounds like you're going to miss
change over time. You're going to miss flows. It sounds like it's
going to be static.
Graham Harmon:
That's been the most common criticism ever since my doctoral
dissertation from some committee members. Here's what I would say.
Constant change, in a way, ends up not giving you much of an
explanation of change.
August:
Sure. That's a good point.
Graham Harmon:
Yeah. Because if everything's changing all the time, why should you
then be interested in revolutions or periods where science changes?
Because a hair falling from my head is also radical change
according to this.
August:
Right. In fact, you could take, say, the economy and say if the
inflation rate is the constant through time, prizes are increasing
all the time, but there's no change really. The [inaudible
00:35:08] would say there's no change there because it's
continuous. Yeah.
Graham Harmon:
Right. Is economics your-
August:
It was, yeah. Yeah.
Graham Harmon:
All right. Great. Yeah. Yes, and you also have, in paleontology,
which is called punctuated equilibrium of Gould and Eldredge,
opposed to Darwinian gradualism. but it turns out in their eyes to
be a better explanation of evolution that it happens quickly
followed by long periods of stability. That's more my own view as
well. That if you're saying everything's changing all the time, you
miss the punctuated aspect of history, that not equally interesting
things are happening at every moment in time.
Graham Harmon:
For example, right now, if I were going into the sciences, I were a
young person, I think I would choose astronomy. Physics, maybe not.
Even though you think of physics as fundamental. That's what you
want to go into. But Lee Smolin lamented in one of his books that
he's part of the first generation of physicists in 500 years that
hasn't made fundamental forward progress. He was quite depressed
about it. Since the standard model in the early '70s, okay. We've
discovered the Higgs-Boson, but that's just fulfilling a prediction
of the standard model. There hasn't really been a huge breakthrough
since then. But if you look at astronomy, well, first of all,
astronomy discovered dark matter and dark energy, so that's coming
from outside physics.
Graham Harmon:
There's also major discoveries happening in astronomy literally
every day. Just open any news website you're probably going to find
an astronomical discovery even before the Webb telescope, which is
just accelerating it. Astronomy is really in a revolutionary phase,
just like physics was in the early 20th century where Rutherford
said, "We live in the heroic age of physics," and he was right. New
discoveries all the time. At any given moment, there are certain
fields where that's happening and others that are a little more
devoted to consolidating what's already known, or to polishing our
understanding. There's different rhythms in different fields, the
different [inaudible 00:36:57].
August:
So the point would be that these points of disruption are become
objects themselves, or that the objects change from one to
another?
Graham Harmon:
I think points of disruption, such as Kuhn's paradigm shifts or
Alain Badiou's events, are points when we no longer can think of a
thing in terms of its qualities. Because the qualities are no
longer internally consistent, they no longer make sense, so we have
to theorize what's deeper than these qualities? That's the object.
What is it that's lying behind this? We're redefining the object.
Einstein essentially redefined what space and time are in his
[inaudible 00:37:37] and general theories of relativity. Some
people try to make the case that, "Oh, Newton's theory is still
true as a special case of Einstein's." I don't think that's right.
I think that Newton's theory is refuted. I agree with Kuhn on this.
Because says that, "Look at something like mass." Both Newton and
Einstein use the concept of mass, but you can't say they're the
same concept. Because in Newton, mass is conserved. In Einstein,
mass is convertible with energy. So they're not really the same
thing, sense. Einstein redefined an object. It might have the same
name, mass, that Newton's hard physical stuff did, but it's not the
same thing. You're redefining the referent of the term.
Graham Harmon:
I'm more on the side that these moments of crisis can lead to
actual different conceptions of the world in terms of the objects
that populate them.
August:
I understand. And the other idea, I think where there's some
tension or I'm not clear how it's handled, is in relationships
between real objects, or in relationships. Because it seems so,
Winnicott said, "There's no such a thing as a baby. There's a
nursing couple before there's a baby." The idea is there's a
relationship that's a real thing in between two objects. My
understanding would be that relationship becomes an object. Or I'm
not sure about that.
Graham Harmon:
Yes. Any real relation will become a new object. The reason for
that is, what defines an object for Triple O is that it has a
reality deeper than our understanding of it, that no understanding
can exhaust. There are certain objects that are false objects. I
can name six random things and say that they comprise an object,
but that object probably doesn't exist outside my thinking of
it.
August:
[inaudible 00:39:31] once you name it does.
Graham Harmon:
It becomes a sensual object at least, then the question [inaudible
00:39:35].
August:
I understand. Yeah.
Graham Harmon:
The question is, at what point does a sensual object become a real
one? Because-
August:
I gotcha.
Graham Harmon:
Sherlock Holmes began as a sensual object in the mind of Arthur
Conan Doyle. But now, in a sense, Sherlock Holmes is a real object.
Because if somebody did a Sherlock Holmes movie where the Holmes
character was not at all convincing, we would say that wasn't
really Sherlock Holmes.
August:
Yeah. That's really good point.
Graham Harmon:
Which some people said about Danny DeVito's Penguin in one of those
Batman movies. It was an interesting character, but it wasn't the
Penguin. [inaudible 00:40:02] critics say that. How can you say it
wasn't the Penguin when the Penguin doesn't exist? Well, because
the [inaudible 00:40:06] does exist in a sense.
August:
Yeah. Right.
Graham Harmon:
You brought up the relation between real objects, and that brings
us back to the second point I forgot to answer about your excellent
summary of Triple O. Which is you talk about the Kantian noumena,
which are things humans can think about but never directly contact.
There is a lot of that in Triple O, and also Heidegger's withdrawn
reality, withdrawn being, that can never be known directly. Some
people accuse Triple O of just rehashing that. But there's a huge
difference, which is that objects are impenetrable to each other.
Also for Triple O. The usual tendency is to say, "Oh, we poor
humans can't reach the in itself. It's our special burden." No. For
Triple O, any relation has that aspect. So, in physical causation,
is not a direct impact. It's an indirect impact. This brings us
into contact with the occasionalist tradition in philosophy, the
idea that nothing can affect anything else directly.
Graham Harmon:
Traditionally, it was thought that God has to bring those things
together, which is not part of the Triple O theory. Because, for
Triple O, no privileged object can be the locus of relation between
all other objects, whether it's God or the human mind. Kant and
Hume simply secularize their occasionalism by saying, "Ah, it's not
God. It's the human mind. All causation's really happening in the
human mind." Either through habit for Hume, or through a category
of the mind for Kant. Whereas, for Triple O, no. It has to be local
in each case. The way we handle that is with the difference between
real and sensual objects. That two real objects can only be
mediated by a sensual object. Because things only encounter the
images of each other.
August:
I see.
Graham Harmon:
[inaudible 00:41:41] itself. Then two sensual objects are only
mediated by a real object. Because on my table now there's my
sensual scotch tape and my sensual book on the Huns. But they're
both connected only through my mind. That's how we get around
it.
August:
We're running out of time. But I thought that was very interesting.
Yeah. You talked about the hard problem, mental life and
consciousness, and you said that's a problem more broadly.
Consciousness in the world, that's a much more broadly than that.
Just to give the listeners a sense of the work that one does,
there's this diagram with the real object and the real qualities,
the sensual object and the sensual qualities. It wouldn't make
sense to try to do this in a podcast. But basically you can look at
the tensions between these and try to capture them through art or
architecture or metaphor. Then there's another concept of a cell,
which is, I understand it would be to take three of these and think
of it as a milieu, or no?
Graham Harmon:
Well, you take two, which combine to a third. Yes. There are three
in that sense. The idea there is that an architectural cell
requires that we not see the human beholder and the artwork as two
separate things. Kant [inaudible 00:43:09] wanted to purify the two
of each other. For Kant, art is really about our minds. But then
Kant's followers in the 20th century, implicit followers like
Clement Greenberg and Michael Fried, did it the other way. For
them, it was the artwork that was important, not the human
beholder. This is why they hated all the post-1960s stuff like
performance art and conceptual art. They thought it was humanizing
the artwork too much. Fried would call it "being too theatrical
about the artwork". Whereas, I would say that art is inherently
theatrical. It requires a beholder. If all humans are extinct, we
don't have any art. We just have a bunch of pieces of canvas
hanging in derelict museums.
Graham Harmon:
Because in order to have art, you need to create that rift between
the object and its qualities, which you don't have, unless there's
some creature capable of apprehending it. I mean, obviously some
animals have aesthetic experience. I don't think there's any
evidence of animals appreciating our artworks are artworks yet.
Maybe I'm wrong. Maybe certain primates understand that paintings
are paintings and can appreciate them on some level. I don't know
with dolphins. I'd be happy to hear that, but I don't personally
know any evidence of that. Certain artworks are made for the human
scale and are not intelligible to non-humans, let's say. Maybe all
artworks. Maybe most. I don't know the exact percentage.
August:
I sense that another aspect of this theory is that it's not so
human-centric.
Graham Harmon:
Yes.
August:
Which is certainly annoying when you look at other theories, and
the human capacity is so much different than anyone else's, than
any other creature's.
Graham Harmon:
Right.
August:
Well, Graham. Professor. It's been great talking to you. I could
talk to you for a few hours. What a large amount of work to do to
grasp architecture. I realize you've been teaching it and that's
helped you say it out loud and get it. But that was quite an
adventure to learn all this stuff, I would think
Graham Harmon:
It is. I would like to always encourage people to realize they can,
if not master a field, they can get up to speed in a few years.
August:
That's what I was really thinking about when I read this. I was
like, "I would never think about taking this on because how many
library floors are devoted to architecture? And how can one come
in, having a PhD in philosophy, and then come in and do that?"
Yeah, no. You have a sort of optimism about that, which then
becomes real.
Graham Harmon:
Way to stay young is keep learning new things. Whether it's new
languages, or new fields. Keeps your brain active, keeps giving you
resistance. And yes, there are endless floors of architecture books
I haven't read them all and neither have the professionals in the
field. But there are certain key joints in the history of any
[inaudible 00:45:53] and you go right for those. Then that creates
a space in which you can learn more details all the time, so I'm
still checking out. I wrote a book on architecture, yes. But I'm
still checking out new architecture books every week from our
library trying to learn them.
August:
Yeah. I thought that your discussion of that show. I guess it was
partly Phillip Johnson and someone else who put together that-
Graham Harmon:
Mark McGee.
August:
Right. That was, yeah. You could tell that was a real key point,
and it really did open everything up. Okay. Great. Well, it's a
great book. Congratulations on it. Architecture and Objects: Art
After Nature. 2022, I think.
Graham Harmon:
Yeah. Just published in July.
August:
Great. Well, it was great talking to you. Appreciate your time very
much.
Graham Harmon:
Thanks, August. I see you have a lot of interesting podcasts on
your site.
August:
I hope so.
Graham Harmon:
Look forward to catching up on those.
August:
Okay. Well, thank you. I appreciate that.
Graham Harmon:
Sure.
August:
I'll talk to you later. Bye.